"[...] for merely theoretical purposes the rule of formation would be very simple. It would merely be to begin by drawing any closed figure, and then proceed [sic] to draw others, subject to the one condition that each is to intersect once and once only all the existing subdivisions produced by those which had gone before." (John Venn, "On the Diagrammatic and Mechanical Representation of Propositions and Reasonings", 1880)
"[…] it must be noticed that these diagrams do not naturally harmonize with the propositions of ordinary life or ordinary logic. […] The great bulk of the propositions which we commonly meet with are founded, and rightly founded, on an imperfect knowledge of the actual mutual relations of the implied classes to one another. […] one very marked characteristic about these circular diagrams is that they forbid the natural expression of such uncertainty, and are therefore only directly applicable to a very small number of such propositions as we commonly meet with." (John Venn, "On the Diagrammatic and Mechanical Representation of Propositions and Reasonings", 1880)
"[...] we can not readily break up a complicated problem into successive steps which can be taken independently. We have, in fact, to solve the problem first, by determining what are the actual mutual relations of the classes involved, and then to draw the circles to represent this final result; we cannot work step-by-step towards the conclusion by aid of our figures." (John Venn, "On the Diagrammatic and Mechanical Representation of Propositions and Reasonings", 1880)
"Whereas the Eulerian plan endeavoured at once and directly to represent propositions, or relations of class terms to one another, we shall find it best to begin by representing only classes, and then proceed to modify these in some way so as to make them indicate what our propositions have to say. How, then, shall we represent all the subclasses which two or more class terms can produce? Bear in mind that what we have to indicate is the successive duplication of the number of subdivisions produced by the introduction of each successive term. and we shall see our way to a very important departure from the Eulerian conception. All that we have to do is to draw our figures, say circles, so that each successive one which we introduce shall intersect once, and once only, all the subdivisions already existing, and we then have what may be called a general framework indicating every possible combination producible by the given class terms." (John Venn, "On the Diagrammatic and Mechanical Representation of Propositions and Reasonings", 1880)
"It will be found that there is a tendency for the resultant outlines thus successively drawn to assume a comb-like shape after the first four or five [...]The fifth-term figure will have two teeth, the sixth four, and so on. [...] There is no trouble in drawing such a diagram for any number of terms which our paper will find room for. But, as has already been repeatedly remarked, the visual aid for which mainly such diagrams exist is soon lost on such a path." (John Venn, "Symbolic Logic", [footnote], 1881)
"There is no need here to exhibit such figures, as they would probably be distasteful to any but the mathematician, and he would see his way to drawing them readily enough for himself [...]" (John Venn, "Symbolic Logic", 1881)
"We endeavour to employ only symmetrical figures, such as should not only be an aid to reasoning, through the sense of sight, but should also be to some extent elegant in themselves." (John Venn, "Symbolic Logic", 1881)
"At the basis of our Symbolic Logic, however represented, whether by words by letters or by diagrams, we shall always find the same state of things. What we ultimately have to do is to break up the entire field before us into a definite number of classes or compartments which are mutually exclusive and collectively exhaustive." (John Venn, "Symbolic Logic" 2nd Ed., 1894)
"The best way of introducing this question will be to enquire a little more strictly whether it is really classes that we thus represent, or merely compartments into which classes may be put? […] The most accurate answer is that our diagrammatic subdivisions, or for that matter our symbols generally, stand for compartments and not for classes. We may doubtless regard them as representing the latter, but if we do so we should never fail to keep in mind the proviso, 'if there be such things in existence'. And when this condition is insisted upon, it seems as if we expressed our meaning best by saying that what our symbols stand for are compartments which may or may not happen to be occupied." (John Venn, "Symbolic Logic" 2nd Ed., 1894)
"My Method of Diagrams resembles Mr. Venn's, in having separate Compartments assigned to the various Classes, and in marking these Compartments as occupied or as empty; but it differs from his Method, in assigning a closed area to the Universe of Discourse, so that the Class which, under Mr. Venn's liberal sway, has been ranging at will through Infinite Space, is suddenly dismayed to find itself "cabin'd, cribb'd, confined" in a limited Cell like any other Class! Also I use rectilinear, instead of curvilinear Figures" (Charles Dogson [Lews Carroll], 1896)
"This is why a 'web' of notes with links (like references) between them is far more useful than a fixed hierarchical system. When describing a complex system, many people resort to diagrams with circles and arrows. Circles and arrows leave one free to describe the interrelationships between things in a way that tables, for example, do not. The system we need is like a diagram of circles and arrows, where circles and arrows can stand for anything." (Tim Berners-Lee, "Information Management: A Proposal", 1989)
"Venn diagrams are widely used to solve problems in set theory and to test the validity of syllogisms in logic. […] However, it is a fact that Venn diagrams are not considered valid proofs, but heuristic tools for finding valid formal proofs." (Sun-Joo Shin, "Situation-Theoretic Account of Valid Reasoning with Venn Diagrams", [in "Logical Reasoning with Diagrams"], 1996)
"Venn diagrams provide us with a formalism that consists of a standardized system of representations, together with rules for manipulating them. In this regard, they could be considered a primitive visual analog of the formal systems of deduction developed in logic." (Jon Barwise & John Etchemendy, "Visual Information and Valid Reasoning", [in "Logical Reasoning with Diagrams"], 1996)
"A Venn diagram is a simple representation of the sample space, that is often helpful in seeing 'what is going on'. Usually the sample space is represented by a rectangle, with individual regions within the rectangle representing events. It is Often helpful to imagine that the actual areas Of the various regions in a Venn diagram are in proportion to the corresponding probabilities. However, there is no need to spend a long time drawing these diagrams - their use is simply as a reminder of what is happening." (Graham Upton & Ian Cook, "Introducing Statistics", 2001)
"Two types of graphic organizers are commonly used for comparison: the Venn diagram and the comparison matrix [...] the Venn diagram provides students with a visual display of the similarities and differences between two items. The similarities between elements are listed in the intersection between the two circles. The differences are listed in the parts of each circle that do not intersect. Ideally, a new Venn diagram should be completed for each characteristic so that students can easily see how similar and different the elements are for each characteristic used in the comparison." (Robert J. Marzano et al, "Classroom Instruction that Works: Research-based strategies for increasing student achievement, 2001)
"It is a curious fact that if you draw an endless line on a piece of paper so that it cuts itself any number of times (but never cuts itself more than once at the same point), then you can color the resulting regions using only two colors without any adjoining regions being the same color. [...] Venn diagrams also possess this property, but for a separate reason, which at first sight seems to be nicely demonstrated by induction." (Anthony W F Edwards, "Cogwheels of the mind: The story of Venn diagrams", 2004)
"The notion of outcomes covering a space is a very useful mental image, as it ties in strongly with the use of Venn diagrams and tables for clarifying the nature of possible events resulting from a trial. There are two important aspects to this. First, when enumerating the various outcomes that comprise an event, the number of (equally. likely) outcomes should correspond, visually, with the area of that part of the diagram represented by the event in question - the greater the probability, the larger the area. Secondly, where events overlap (for example, when rolling a die, consider the two events 'getting an even score' and 'getting a score greater than 2' ), the various regions in the Venn diagram help to clarify the various combinations of events that might occur.
"Venn diagrams visually ground symbolic logic and abstract set operations. They do not ground probability. Their common overuse in introducing probability, especially in teaching, can have undesirable consequences." (R W Oldford & W H Cherry, "Picturing Probability: the poverty of Venn diagrams, the richness of Eikosograms", 2006)